Skip all menusSkip 
first menu
Français Government of Canada BioPortal    
Home Site Map News Room FAQ Search
cbac-cccb
Browse
Features
About Us
Meeting Minutes
Publications
Advice
Annual Reports
Consultations
Project Reports
Research
2005
2004
2003
2002
2001
2000
1999
Topics
Biotech Watch
News Room
Dialogue Tool
Glossary









Canadian Biotechnology Advisory Committee
Home Publications Research 2001

Towards an Adequate Ethical Framework for Setting Biotechnology Policy

Prepared For

The Canadian Biotechnology Advisory Committee Stewardship Standing Committee

By Susan Sherwin1
January 2001

Table of Contents

  1. Introduction
  2. Biotechnology
    1. Genetic Testing
    2. Genetically Modified Food
  3. Available Value Systems
  4. The Public Interest
  5. Moral Dimensions (1): Procedural Ethics
  6. Moral Dimensions (2): Concepts
    1. Autonomy
    2. Justice
  7. Responsibilities
  8. Conclusion
  9. Works Consulted

  1. Introduction

    Biotechnology has the power to generate major social change. Already, biotechnology has had an impact on the lives of Canadian citizens and it invites us to reconsider some fundamental Canadian values and attitudes. It seems certain that its influence will increase over time. Such power carries with it significant moral responsibilities; hence, proper management of this technology requires careful moral deliberation. It is, therefore, essential to determine what particular moral values and practices should guide policy in this realm.

    This paper is intended to identify and explicate some of the fundamental ethical components needed for establishing a morally adequate national biotechnology policy. It is organized to first clarify its use of the term “biotechnology” and then to introduce two key examples of biotechnology that will be used to illuminate the subsequent discussion. Next, it will propose a multi-part ethical framework to guide moral deliberations regarding biotechnology policy. It shall than explore some of the ways in which these various moral considerations can be translated into assignments of specific responsibilities.

  2. Biotechnology

    In order to develop an ethical framework to guide policymaking in the realm of biotechnology, the first challenge is to determine the scope of the subject matter. The fluid and ambiguous use of the term “biotechnology” adds to the complexity of setting ethical standards, since the target of proposed guidelines seems to be so extensive and diverse.2 This ambiguity is evident in the 1998 documents produced by the Canadian Biotechnology Strategy Task Force to promote public discussion of government policy and it is repeated in the summary document pursuant to those consultations.3 The principal Roundtable Consultation Document (CBS 1998a) initially defines biotechnology as “an umbrella term that covers a broad spectrum of scientific tools …[using] living organisms, or parts of living organisms to make new products or provide new methods of production” (CBS 1998a, p. 3). The examples that follow are of such familiar, unthreatening practices as the use of yeast to produce beer, bread and wine.4 But the reassuring impact of associations with long-standing technologies is misleading since, in fact, the term “biotechnology” is primarily used to refer to the many new technologies that identify and manipulate genetic information or modify genetic structures. In fact, just a few lines later, the very same document quickly makes clear that its own focus is with “biotechnology’s newer techniques, such as genetic engineering or DNA-based technology. . . [including] the modification or duplication of genetic information or its transfer from one organism to another”(CBS 1998a, p. 3).5

    I shall follow the practice of the Consultation documents and concentrate my discussion on genetically based forms of technology. I, too, shall concentrate on biotechnologies in the realms of health and food production since the principal current uses of biotechnology fall within these spheres. The Consultation documents make a persuasive case for the beneficial potential of these forms of technology. They claim that all Canadians can hope to benefit from these technologies (CBS 1998b, 2), echoing the enthusiasm of the many authors who welcome the benefits available through effective and efficient use of biotechnologies, especially in health and food production (e.g., Brown 2000; Fletcher 1998; Grace 1997; Khoury 1996).

    Before exploring some of the moral questions associated with these implicitly hopeful forms of biotechnology, however, I shall briefly diverge from the approach taken in the Consultation documents. Where these documents refer only to socially promising areas of biotechnology innovation, I wish to be clear that some forms of biotechnology are morally objectionable from the very start. Biotechnology holds the promise of creating, as well as relieving, enormous amounts of suffering. For example, it is the source of weapons of biological warfare which have enormous potential for harm to humans and other living things. Biotechnology also provides the means for unprecedented levels of terrorist threats by facilitating production of powerfully toxic materials with relatively little infrastructure required for deployment. It also facilitates efficient eugenics programs and practices of human genetic enhancement that alter our approach to human reproduction and diversity. As well, many forms of biotechnology carry with them the power, and the demand, to invade areas that were formerly considered the realm of private, personal information (Murray and Botkin 1995; Shulman 2000). It does not take much imagination, then, to find cause for worry about the implications of growing knowledge in biotechnology. Policy makers must confront honestly the power for harm as well as benefit that is inherent in these new technological tools. It is disturbing that the Consultation documents (CBS 1998a) and the subsequent statement of the Canadian Biotechnology Strategy (1998b) fail even to acknowledge these dangers.6

    I shall now rejoin the agenda set by the Consultation documents and refrain from further discussion of forms of biotechnology that can be straightforwardly judged to be primarily harmful. In contrast to those documents, however, I shall also resist the presumption that many of the technologies can be simply accepted as wholly beneficial. I shall concentrate on the messy but crowded middle ground of technologies that have mixed effects, i.e., on forms of biotechnology whose benefits are accompanied by risks, either to their users or to others. To represent this broad area, I shall look at two types of biotechnology, one each from the domains of health and food production, the two principal realms of current applications. I shall briefly review some of the potential benefits and potential harms associated with each type of technology.

    1. Genetic Testing

      According to the Consultation documents, “more than 90 percent of the advanced biotechnology products on the world market are related to health”(CBS 1998a, p. 3). In the Health Sector Consultation Document (Health Canada et al. 1998), four different areas of activity are identified in the chapter titled “Health Protection”: surveillance, diagnosis, treatment, and prevention. In each category, there are important ethical questions to raise about the ultimate impact of existing and anticipated technologies. Let us focus specifically on genetic testing, an activity associated with both surveillance and diagnosis (and, ideally, also with prevention). Genetic testing is said to be able to “confirm the presence of a particular disease, indicate that the disease will occur in the future or reveal an increased susceptibility to a disease” (Health Canada 1998, p. 4). It is these latter, future-oriented uses that concern me here.

      The attraction of such tests is clear. In this era of scientific medicine, it seems axiomatic that the more knowledge available about disease paths, the greater the likelihood of successfully preventing illness. For many types of disease, early detection significantly improves the prospects of cure or at least effective management (Bansal 2000). Early diagnosis of most forms of cancer, for instance, tends to improve the odds of long-term survival. Hence, it seems reasonable to hope that early identification of genetic susceptibility to a disease will provide individuals with knowledge that might help them to avoid contracting that disease. For example, knowledge of higher than average susceptibility to certain forms of heart disease may motivate someone to exercise more frequently, eat a healthier diet, and avoid smoking (Murray and Botkin 1995).

      Of course, the value of this tailored advice is uncertain, since, for the most part, it consists of public health advice already recommended to everyone. Since no one is invulnerable to heart disease, everyone has reason to follow the rules of a heart-healthy lifestyle. Those who know there is a history of heart disease in their family are, generally, already aware of the need for extra vigilance. It is unclear how helpful it will be for them to learn that they face a specific degree of risk for developing some particular variation of heart disease. In any case, a negative test indicating that they do not carry the gene that affects family members with early heart disease could not be interpreted as a license to smoke or give up exercise, although it might have that effect.

      Not only may this information prove less helpful than we might hope, it could turn out to be harmful. One difficulty is that this technology represents “diagnosis” of probable future, not current, illness. In other words, it is a means for creating a category of people who are “pre-symptomatically ill.” The implications of such a label are very problematic. For one thing, many people with a higher than average susceptibility to a disease will never contract that disease though many will come to think of themselves, or of certain body parts, as “ticking time bombs” (Bluman 1999; Geller et al 1997; Parens 1996).

      Consider how the first general genetic test of a “susceptibility to disease” aimed at a large, currently healthy adult population has unfolded. This is the test for BRCA 1 and 2, a set of genetic anomalies associated with five to ten percent of breast cancers (Inglehart et al 1998). This test is intended for women with a family history of certain types of breast cancer. While a positive test does not definitively signal that a woman will develop breast cancer (nor a negative test that she won’t), women who test positive for either of these genes do face a relatively high risk of developing the disease at some time in their lives. The strategies available to them to reduce this risk are grim. Minimally, they will be advised to undergo constant monitoring and frequent testing. They may be advised to undergo a prophylactic double mastectomy and also removal of their ovaries and/or to begin taking the powerfully toxic drug tomoxifen with its many serious side effects (Schrag et al 2000).7 In addition, they may lose access to health insurance and possibly also face loss of employment and, in some cases, of partners in intimate relationships. They will also be faced with the personal dilemma of deciding what to tell their sisters and daughters (Steel et al 1999).8

      There are other levels of problems present with these technologies that go beyond the difficult risk-benefit calculations faced by individual users. Michel Foucault (1973) argued that routine medical surveillance encourages each individual to internalize the gaze of the clinician to the point that we experience our bodies not directly as aspects of our very selves, but indirectly as objects for expert approval or concern. In the constant monitoring implicit in adopting the clinical gaze to our selves, we treat our bodies (and sometimes our minds) as imperfect objects in need of regular clinical attention and adjustment. Use of genetic testing to expand the repertoire of routine clinical surveillance fosters the alienating assumption that dangerous disease may erupt at any time and we are dependent on expert intervention to recognize and respond to such events. This is a cultural phenomenon, outside of the control of any particular individual. So, even if someone makes the private choice to forgo some of these genetic surveillance/diagnostic technologies (e.g., genetic and imaging testing for breast cancer), she will still be confronted by a cultural understanding of her body as an appropriate object of routine monitoring.

      Moreover, the very development and normalization of genetic testing technologies contribute to the social phenomenon that Abby Lippman (1991; 1998) has dubbed “geneticization.” This is the tendency to assume that genes alone are primarily responsible for our health status, that genetic explanations can account for the major physical and behavioural differences among people, and that the solution to most health problems can be found through genetic knowledge and manipulation. Geneticization ignores the fact that genes act in specific environments and seldom provide unambiguous evidence of an individual’s traits or prospects.9 The attitude of geneticization detracts attention from social and environmental factors (e.g., poor nutrition) that are known to affect health in favour of efforts to identify and respond to individual genetic variations.10

      This tendency to overlook social and environmental dimensions of health in favour of biological features is not unique to the technologies of genetic testing for susceptibility to disease. It is common to many other technological innovations in health care. Each carries with it the costs of lost opportunities to pursue other strategies for improving the health of Canadians and others (Gorenstein 1996). As governments encourage and support investment in biotech solutions to health problems, they are likely to find themselves with fewer resources – financial and human – available to pursue other strategies for improving people’s health. Focus on genetic testing and other types of technological solutions to health problems tends to fall within a biomedical worldview that assumes health problems are best addressed by identifying and correcting flaws within individual patients. The approach of looking for genetic pre-dispositions to disease in order to try to modify an individual’s life experience (or, someday, her genetic makeup) is based on the problematic assumptions that the social and physical environments she inhabits are acceptable as they are and that we need only ensure that individuals are better adapted to their environment. Moreover, insofar as genetic testing drains limited public resources away from needed social reforms and creates confusion about the role of social factors in illness and injustice, it may well work against the overall health interests of disadvantaged members of society (Bowman 1995; Caplan 1994; Lebacqz 1998; Sagar et al 2000).

    2. Genetically Modified Food

      On the food production front, it is again easy to see the potential advantages of biotechnology. For example, the consultation documents speak enthusiastically about the capacity of transgenic crops and animals to improve global nutrition. In particular, advances in biotechnology are said to be “the key to increasing the world’s food production in the face of environmental concerns, limited arable land and population increases” (CBS 1998a, 2). In addition, the Health Sector Consultation Document lists several ways in which agricultural biotechnology can contribute to human health and well-being. It lists: “the development of more healthful food with higher nutritional quality”; crop modifications that will lead to the virtual elimination of “human and animal nutritional deficiencies”; improved “availability of therapeutic products”; production of “an inexpensive and abundant supply of compounds with potential health benefits”; and disease prevention “by enhancing the levels of those compounds in food that are known to have beneficial physiological effects” (e.g., carotenoids and quercetina); and the “development of new foods for Canadians who suffer from food intolerance disorders” (e.g. coeliac disease). (Health Canada et al 1998, 6-7).

      Exciting as these prospects are, however, there is significant public wariness about transgenic foods. The Canadian Biotechnology Strategy makes reference to public concerns, but describes them as a result of “information gaps” and lack of “consumer awareness and understanding” (CBS 1998b, 2-3), implicitly dismissing any empirical basis for worry. All concerns cannot be reduced, however, to questions of ignorance, superstition, or resistance to change. There are some solid scientific arguments identifying risks attached to some agricultural uses of biotechnology.11

      Some of the concerns are quite familiar: many people worry about the safety of foods produced through transgenic molecular transformations. For example, there is widespread worry that genetically modified foods carry a certain risk of generating new food-borne allergies. These worries stem from the fact that genetic modifications involve introduction of new proteins to traditional foods, and allergies are protein-based (FAO/WHO 2000). Some fear that transmission of genes from one species to another may be accompanied by transmission of new micro-organisms or new types of toxic substances to which humans have not had time to evolve adequate resistance (FAO/WHO 2000). Moreover, some of the effects feared may not be immediately apparent. Yet, the rapid changes generated by biotechnology do not allow much time for full investigation of long-term effects and many critics believe that there is often inadequate safety testing of new products ( De Angelis 1992; Goldsmith et al 1992; Pimm 1991).

      Another common concern has to do with the environmental impact of the introduction of newly manufactured agricultural species. There is worry about the ways that new species (or, more likely, modifications of existing species) will affect the ecology into which they are placed (Fox 1996; Mikkelson et al 1996; Paulkaitis and Roossinck 1996). The fact that agricultural practices have historically always damaged existing ecologies (Thompson 2000) is of little comfort to citizens worried about rapidly expanded environmental degradation. Of particular concern to environmentalists is the fact that most of the uses of agricultural biotechnology to date have been aimed at developing plants that are more tolerant of herbicides and pesticides than other plants; that is, they are designed to allow greater use of certain toxic chemicals in agriculture (Goldsmith and Hildyard 1990; Shiva 1993).12

      Moreover, there are reasons to worry even about the promise expressed in the consultation documents of the ability of biotechnology to help to feed the hungry in the developing world. Of particular concern has been the development of “genetic use restriction technology” (GURTs) designed to create sterile seeds. Known by such intimidating trade names as “Terminator” and “Traitor,” these are genes whose sole purpose is to ensure the failure of reproduction in second-generation plants. The introduction of such genes may be important if wide scale production of some genetically modified crops does result in serious environmental threats, since, in theory at least, the use of these genes will permit effective termination of dangerous new species. But their routine use also means that farmers who plant the genetically-altered seeds will be unable to rely on the age-old tradition of using seeds harvested from one year’s crop to produce the next. They will be compelled to return each year to the manufacturer for a new supply that can be sold at whatever price the market will bear. Moreover, this technology will allow producers to engineer seeds to perform only with the application of specially designed fertilizers or pesticides. It is, then, a technology that will increase the dependence of farmers on marketers of seeds and related products; such a change is very likely to increase the costs of farming. For subsistence farmers in particular, this is likely to be a devastating change. The potential for accelerated – rather than reduced – rates of malnutrition in the developing world is significant (Goldsmith and Hildyard 1991; Shiva 1993).13

      In a similar vein, questions have been raised about the likelihood that biotechnology will actually improve nutrition in the developing world. The most frequently touted example of the nutritional value of biotechnology to the developing world is the production of genetically engineered Vitamin A enriched rice (so-called Golden Rice). This project is still years from release. Moreover, although it has been developed through public funding, the research has been turned over to a multinational seed producer (AstraZeneca, now Syngenta) for patenting and marketing (RAFI September/October 2000). Thus, its ultimate availability and the impact it will have on the health of people in poor countries are still difficult to measure. In the meantime, industry-based researchers are primarily pursuing nutritional plant modifications aimed at more affluent consumers.

      The conundrums evident in even these cursory discussions of but two varieties of biotechnology make evident the necessity of attending to ethical values in setting policies regulating the development and introduction of specific forms of biotechnology. The potential consequences for specific innovations in each type of biotechnology – and for the changes likely to be wrought by the combined impact of multiple examples of each sort of technology – are great. In some cases singly, and, surely, collectively, they can be expected to make dramatic changes in the lives of individuals and societies.

      Moreover, the impact of these technologies is unlikely to be evenly distributed. It is readily apparent that certain types of risks largely fall either on those who choose to invest in particular technologies or on the immediate consumers of that technology. Less apparent is the fact that there are other types of risks that primarily threaten individuals who, as third parties, have no direct control over the deployment of the technology. For instance, siblings of individuals who choose genetic testing may be refused health or life insurance unless they agree to undergo the same tests (Boetzkes 1999; Rhodes 1998; Steele et al 1999). And salmon fishers may find their livelihood destroyed by the impact of pesticides created to work in combination with certain genetically modified crops (Birmingham and Tinker 1999; Tangwa 1999). It is the responsibility of governments to protect the interests of everyone affected by the new technologies, whether by direct consumption or by accidental “fall-out.” Given the complex and mixed sorts of consequences associated with these technologies, it is especially urgent that public policy be grounded in clear moral analysis.

  3. Available Value Systems

    In order to conduct the requisite moral analysis, we need to appeal to an adequate ethical framework that will help us to identify and explore the full range of moral values at issue. In particular, we need to find ways to ensure recognition and adequate analysis of all relevant moral considerations. While many ethicists would recommend adoption of a particular moral theory as the framework for all moral inquiry, I do not believe that any single value system can capture and order all the relevant moral considerations. Therefore, I propose that we concentrate on two complementary strategies (one procedural and the other substantive) that can jointly help to ensure that adequate attention gets paid to all relevant moral considerations.

    First, though, I shall offer a brief explanation for why I resist selection of a single theoretical perspective. This resistance derives from my appreciation of the fact that there are many different value systems that could be invoked to help set policy governing biotechnology. As I have argued elsewhere, selection of any particular value system largely determines the sorts of ethical considerations one perceives as relevant to the question explored (Sherwin 1999, Sherwin 2000). If we adopt a consequentialist (utilitarian) moral framework, for example, we will concentrate (solely) on trying to anticipate and compare the likely consequences of alternative policy options. In contrast, if we adopt a deontological (duty-oriented) moral perspective, our attention will be directed towards trying to ensure that the policies in question are consistent with a set of fundamental moral obligations. Because both sorts of considerations have moral weight, both should be part of our moral deliberations. So, too, should important moral aspects of the problem that are suggested by such other major moral theories as ethics of care and feminist ethics.14 Different moral theories help develop our moral perceptual capacities in complementary directions. No single theoretical perspective will suffice to capture all of the morally relevant aspects of the policy options under review.

    Thus, when approaching complex policy matters, we should actively seek out moral perspectives that help to identify and explore as many moral dimensions of the problem as possible. This requires us to pursue deliberative strategies that will promote sensitivity to the multiple moral considerations that are relevant to the issues before us. Nevertheless, the identification of morally relevant factors does not always produce a unique moral solution. Hence, even if we were able to identify all the morally relevant aspects of a situation, we might still not know how to resolve the specific moral dilemma before us. Although these substantive moral tools (theories) will exclude certain options, they sometimes fail to select a single best solution. In such cases, we must rely on effective strategies that can produce an ethically acceptable decision. Only an ethically adequate procedure can resolve these various types of ambiguity.

    We need, then, to make use of two complementary approaches, one procedural and the other substantive. While I shall discuss these two strategies separately, in practice they should be pursued simultaneously in an integrated fashion. Together, they provide some of the key tools necessary to ensure the requisite consideration of diverse moral perspectives throughout the policy setting process. Interestingly, both come together in one realm of moral consideration inherent in the setting of public policy: the public interest. I shall begin explication of these complementary aspects of moral deliberation by reflecting on the topic of the public interest because it makes use of both procedural and substantive dimensions of ethics and because it seems to be the subject most central to government’s role in managing biotechnology development and use.

  4. The Public Interest

    The scale and dimensions of possible consequences arising from biotechnology innovations supports a strong moral argument for establishing public policies that will manage the complex array of benefits and risks attached to these technologies in the best interests of Canadians. Indeed, the entire consultation exercise, aimed at producing a revised national biotechnology policy, is an implicit statement of the federal government’s sense of responsibility to influence the development and production of biotechnologies in Canada. The various Consultation documents explicitly acknowledge the government’s sense of responsibility to develop a comprehensive and coherent biotechnology policy that is centred on “Canadian values” (CBS 1998b, 8). That policy consists of a vision (or statement of the ideal pursued), a set of guiding (normative) principles, and a defined set of specific goals (CBS 1998b, 8-9).15 Each of these components involves a normative (or value-laden) dimension and represents particular ethical choices that merit careful scrutiny.

    Government must assume leadership in setting biotechnology policy. It is simply not possible for individuals acting alone to protect themselves from some of the potential hazards of this technology, nor is it likely that individuals will be able to take full advantage of many of the benefits without collective action. Hence, it is essential that government take the initiative and develop and implement policies that will protect the well-being of its citizens and preserve society’s valued institutions. This moral responsibility is commonly described as a duty to act in the public interest.

    It is, therefore, striking that none of the Consultation documents make any explicit reference to the concept of the public interest. The closest they come is to express an underlying intent to promote the interests of Canadians. The primary Roundtable Consultation Document begins by declaring its agenda is to find “. . . mechanisms to ensure that biotechnology products enhance our health, quality of life and environment as they generate jobs and economic growth” (CBS 1998a, 1). It goes on to report that “The Government of Canada is working with partners to determine the best ways and means to realize the potential benefits of biotechnology for Canadians” (CBS 1998a, 1). Its proposed vision is “For Canada to be a world leader in biotechnology and through it, to enhance the quality of life of Canadians in terms of health, safety, the environment and economic development” (CBS 1998a, 8). The post-Consultation Document offers a no longer qualified version of the Vision where the components remain (almost) the same, but the order of emphasis has shifted:
    The CBS vision is:

    To enhance the quality of life of Canadians in terms of health, safety, the environment and social and economic development by positioning Canada as a responsible world leader in biotechnology. (CBS 1998b, 8, emphasis in original) We can, presumably, infer from such statements that the Government of Canada is pursuing these goals in terms of its over-arching responsibility to protect and promote the public interest.

    The absence of an explicit reference to the public interest could be a reflection of the ambiguity attached to the term “public interest.” It is a vague concept that has political theorists divided about the value of its use. “The public” does not appear to be a single entity with clear and obvious interests. It consists of many different individuals and groups who have diverse, overlapping, and sometimes conflicting interests. Nonetheless, there is some common ground. Most modern theorists can at least agree with John Locke that the state has a duty to safeguard the natural rights of individuals. Many define the public interest as protection of individual rights and provision of fair procedures for arbitrating between competing interests in an impartial way (Benn 1967). (In other words, while commitment to the public interest seems to be commitment to a substantive moral value, it is best pursued through procedural efforts.)

    Some theorists, for example Virginia Held (1984), have suggested that we use the concept of the common good to represent specific things that are of benefit to all members of a state. Thus, the term “common good” stands for the things that are of shared interest to all members of society. Held cites the example of avoiding nuclear holocaust as a clear case of a common good: every member of society has an interest in this state of affairs. Similarly, it is in the common good to avoid ecological disaster such as destruction of fresh water supplies by overuse of toxic agricultural chemicals.

    To complicate matters yet further, there is a third concept to be considered, namely that of collective goods. Collective goods are benefits that can only be achieved through collective action. For example, legal contracts can only exist within the context of a state and a form of legal institution. There is no such thing as a private legal system (although there certainly are some that favour particular private interests). There are also many services that are only practical if citizens cooperate in establishing and supporting them: for example, health care, national defense, policing and firefighting, and pollution controls are services that benefit everyone and are best run as public institutions. While many collective goods are also common goods, some are not since some practices that require collective action across a society fail to benefit all members of that society. (An extreme example would be a legally sanctioned institution of slavery.)

    A system of regulation and evaluation of new biotechnologies is a collective good in that it can only be achieved through collective action. To show that it is also part of the common good, we would need to demonstrate that (virtually) all citizens benefit from such a system. Given the scale of risks and potential benefits of many new biotechnologies, it seems likely that a publicly supported structure to evaluate and regulate new biotechnologies would fit into the category of common good as well as that of collective good.16 Moreover, such a system falls within the technical sense of the public interest since some biotechnologies may threaten the human rights of members of society. For example, use of genetic tests to exclude people with a susceptibility to some form of cancer from certain occupations would raise human rights concerns.

    In popular usage, the term “public interest” is used to capture all three concepts. That is, it includes not only the technical interpretation (i.e., protection of individual rights and fair procedures for arbitrating among competing interests), but also promotion of common goods and of collective goods requiring state coordination. There are, in other words, substantive values sought by citizens in the development of public policies. Citizens depend on their governments to put in place safety provisions that will ensure no new technologies will be introduced that might bring serious harm to them or to the society they depend upon.17 When the impact of specific technologies is unclear or when the benefits and risks are unevenly distributed, they expect government to establish appropriate procedures to decide when to authorize implementation and when to demand restrictions. It is common to read public interest as including such institutions as are needed to protect citizens from foreseeable harms as well as those required to promote the welfare of all.

    In this sense, the public interest has both positive and negative dimensions; that is, it reflects an interest in promoting well-being and also an interest in avoiding harms. Governments have a responsibility to attend to both types of concerns, and the Consultation Documents, especially the post-consultation document (CBS1998b), cite commitments to both sorts of activities.18 When these two goals conflict, governments must decide on which should take priority. It is the potential for serious conflict between the welfare of some and the risks faced by others that makes biotechnology policy so fraught with difficulty.

    The tone of the Consultation documents makes clear that the Canadian government is preoccupied by its responsibility to attend to the positive dimension of the public interest. The documents insist that a strong biotechnology policy will benefit Canadians and thereby serve the positive dimension of its regard for the public interest. For instance, one of the goals listed for the biotechnology renewal process is to ensure “that biotechnology is developed responsibly for the maximum benefits of Canadians, both now and in the future” (CBS 1998a, 1). The post-consultation document opens with a description of biotechnology as offering “significant economic benefits, particularly in exports and job creation, as well as important health, safety and environmental benefits” (CBS 1998b, 1). While the documents circulated before the public consultations were unclear as to whether the goal is to benefit all Canadians, most Canadians, or merely some Canadians, the later document promises explicitly that “All Canadians … will benefit from the new transformation” (CBS 1998b, 2).

    In its implicit interpretation of the public interest as residing with a policy that maximizes the benefits of biotechnology, the Biotechnology Strategy Task Force has chosen to “accentuate the positive” and largely ignore the negative possibilities of biotechnology development. Indeed, as noted above, the consultation documents are filled with examples of the possible benefits that will flow from biotechnology; they make no explicit reference to the potential harms. Even the post-consultation document, while reporting on the wariness expressed by Canadians regarding the risks of some biotechnologies, speaks primarily of “gaps in consumer awareness and understanding” (CBS 1998b, 3), not of actual hazards associated with some technologies. In casting its lot in favour of fostering positive benefits, these documents implicitly commit government to a default position that places the burden of proof on those who would limit development of technology. That is, they presume the overall benefit of development in biotechnology and resist placing limits on new technologies unless well-defined issues of safety can be shown.

    This approach departs from popular sentiment and from some important international conventions. Public and scientific concerns about the inherent risks associated with many forms of biotechnology are expressed in the widely cited precautionary principle. This principle has been enshrined in numerous international treaties and declarations, including the United Nations Rio Declaration on Environment and Development (UN 1992) and the Treaty on European Union (1992). Unfortunately, there is no single authoritative definition available for this widely recommended principle.19 In an attempt to fill this vacuum, an international group of scientists, government officials, lawyers, and environmental activists met in January 1998 at Wingspread in Wisconsin and drafted a consensus statement. The statement identified four parts to the precautionary principle:
    1. People have a duty to take anticipatory action to prevent harm.
    2. The burden of proof of harmlessness of a new technology, process, activity, or chemical lies with the proponents, not the general public.
    3. Before using a new technology, process, or chemical, or starting a new activity, people have an obligation to examine “a full range of alternatives” including the alternative of doing nothing.
    4. Decisions applying the precautionary principle must be “open, informed, and democratic” and “must include affected parties.” (Wingspread 1998)

    In other words, the precautionary principle expresses the requirement that concern about risks must be considered before proceeding with the development of any new technology. It requires that new technologies only be pursued if they can be shown to be harmless or necessary. The emphasis is placed on the negative dimension of the public interest by insisting on the duty to protect the public from future harms.

    The precautionary principle is subject to considerable, vigorous debate and its precise interpretation involves moral and political analysis. Nonetheless, given the prominence of the precautionary principle in other nations’ approach to biotechnology and in various international agreements – including some that Canada has signed (e.g., the 1992 Rio Declaration on the Environment) – it is striking that discussion of this principle is wholly absent from the Consultation documents. As the Pollara and Earnscliffe (2000) study demonstrates, most Canadians assume that something like this principle is already in effect in Canada. Certainly, many knowledgeable Canadians have proposed a version of the precautionary principle as the basis for Canadian biotechnology policy (e.g., the Canadian Institute for Environmental Law and Policy).20 It seems, then, that we need Canadian debate on the appropriate interpretation of this principle and a formal process for determining which version of it Canadians want to endorse. The underlying spirit of protection of individual and collective interests has a fundamental role to play in government’s responsibilities to the public interest.

    Now that we have seen one sphere in which substantive and procedural ethical questions are deeply intertwined, it is time to look more closely at these two aspects of moral deliberation and see how disentangling them can illuminate the prominent role of each.

  5. Moral Dimensions (1): Procedural Ethics

    Procedural approaches to ethics are essential since, in many cases, it is difficult to specify a precise moral solution to a problem.21 There is no objective Archimedian point from which one can survey all relevant moral perspectives and confidently identify the morally best answer. Particularly in the face of complex issues where reasonable people disagree about the morally appropriate response, it is often preferable to establish fair procedures for addressing difficult matters than to try to decide from the outset the moral conclusions that should be binding. Indeed, part of the motivation for establishing the Canadian Biotechnology Advisory Committee (CBAC) is that it can provide meaningful debate to help inform government policy in this complex area. The procedural question, then, is how should CBAC go about fulfilling its mandate to foster debate and help to resolve moral conflicts.

    Perhaps the most straightforward task CBAC faces is establishing where there are matters that fall within the scope of the common good in the realm of biotechnology. An example of this is the establishment of reasonable procedures to make certain that no products are introduced that will cause significant harm to the health of Canadians, to the environment, or to the economy on which Canadian prosperity depends. Such procedures would include a system to monitor safety and efficacy of products, as well as honesty in communication. Consideration of the common good requires attention to the long-term as well as the short-term impacts of various technological innovations evaluated in terms of their effects on the well-being of Canadians and Canadian society. As noted above, it entails adoption of specific measures that will protect as well as promote the public interest, such as the precautionary principle.

    Beyond these specific examples of common Canadian interests, I suggest there is also a shared interest in acting morally on a global scale; such an interest is a clear example of a collective good, in that it can only be achieved through collective action to regulate individual initiatives. This type of consideration requires the development of policies aimed at ensuring that our government and industries do not engage in practices that undermine the welfare of people in economically vulnerable parts of the world.22

    As I argued above, government has a moral duty to protect and promote the public interest of justly arbitrating among competing interests by establishing fair procedures that are responsive to the full range of interests at stake. A principal difficulty in fulfilling this duty is that of identifying the many interests that may be involved. Developing skills at moral perception (through knowledge of multiple ethical theories and knowledge of different cultural perspectives) can help to make clear where many of the relevant interests lie (Sherwin 2000). But it is also essential to put in place an open and responsive process that will allow input from those whose interests might often be overlooked or misunderstood.

    Typically, bodies asked to adjudicate among conflicting interests invite representatives to meet and seek a mediated or negotiated resolution of the conflict. In such circumstances, it is appropriate to use the language of “stakeholders” and invite interested parties from affected groups to participate jointly in providing policy advice. In the context of biotechnology, obvious stakeholders are researchers, producers, and consumers. Each group has explicit interests at stake that may, or may not, coincide with the interests of others, so it is important to have representatives of each of the affected groups actively engaged to identify and promote their specific interests.

    It is not always obvious, however, who should count as a stakeholder. Often those who will be most profoundly affected by a policy do not perceive its effects in advance. For example, if a form of agricultural biotechnology pollutes the environment by generating increased use of chemical fertilizers, many people who had not thought of themselves as having any “positive” interest in the development of the technology may be seriously harmed by its use. Alternatively, if some type of technology such as genetic testing for a predisposition to Alzheimer’s Disease becomes the norm, then many people will find themselves required to make use of such testing whether they wish to or not.23 One of the reasons consumer groups object to the sale of unlabeled genetically modified foods is the fact that the absence of labels prevents consumers from being able to avoid these types of products if that is their intent. Many of the people who ultimately become stakeholders by virtue of imposition of new products on their lives do not immediately perceive their eventual interest in the policy in question. In other cases, people are affected by practices to which they have no direct connection. For example, many people with disabilities argue that that their community is affected by the validation of prejudicial public attitudes against disabilities that is implicit in the routine use by others of prenatal testing of fetuses (Asch and Geller 1996).

    Thus, the public interest in protecting human rights and arbitrating between competing interests can only be properly served by taking measures to ensure that all relevant interests are represented. One important strategy for this end is to include in the discussion participants who will look beyond the expressed interests of those who identify as stakeholders. This role is typically played either by experts who assume a position of neutrality or by citizens who have no expressed prior self-interest in the outcome. In fact, a full exploration of relevant moral perspectives is likely to require both types of participants. Experts can bring needed background information to the table, and citizen participants bring a position of concerned public interest. Both act in ways that are distinctly different from that of identified stakeholders whose role is defined as representative of specific sets of interests.

    There is another type of participant that should be present at the table as well, and that is citizen activists who have taken a specific interest in the policies in question. Typically associated with grass roots or not-for-profit NGOs (non-government organizations), these individuals have actively investigated the subject matter and seek political influence in the relevant policies. They are not stakeholders in the usual sense, for they do not stand to benefit personally from introduction of the technologies in question, though they do provide a specific point of view that must be present in discussions. (Generally, they speak from an interested, but not a self-interested position.) Often, they represent the indirect interests of people who will be affected by technologies without specifically choosing to make use of them. This type of person brings important information and defined interests to the debate and, therefore, offers a perspective that must be heard in policy-making forums.

    The distinction between the role of citizen and the role of stakeholder should be as clear as possible. It is not that stakeholders are not citizens, or that citizens do not have interests; rather, it is that participation as representative of a specific interest group is quite different from participation as a concerned citizen acting in the interest of the collective good of the public interest. Both roles are important when seeking a policy that adjudicates among competing interests, but they are not equivalent and they must not be confused with one another.

    Nor should the role of citizen be reduced to that of consumer. Consumers of technology are stakeholders with defined interests: they need safe, reliable, affordable products supported by accurate information and protection from exploitation. When wearing their consumer hats, such people will assume that the products in question will be developed and marketed and they will seek to influence the terms of their distribution. In contrast, those acting primarily as citizens – that is, acting without specified interests – will want to be able to question the value of even pursuing some products. They will be expected to reflect on the likely impact these products will have on society as a whole, not just on those who choose to acquire or employ them.24

    Moreover, it is especially important that panels charged with adjudicating among competing interests be attentive to voices that are most frequently overlooked in society. They should be particularly attentive to the situation of groups who bear the greatest risks if particular technologies are implemented. They should be aware of ways in which existing structures favour some social groups at the expense of others in order to take steps to avoid repeating these patterns (Bulger 1996; Bowman 1995; Dove 2000; Lebacqz a998). Representatives of groups that are already disadvantaged in society and stand to lose more ground with the introduction of certain technologies should be granted special status. For example, people with disabilities should be present at debates about expanded genetic testing programs, and those focused on hunger in the developing world must be present when decisions are made regarding approval of patents on such life staples as Basmati rice.25 The role of such representatives is distinctly different both from that of representatives of groups who stand to benefit from the technology in question and also from that of generic citizen participants who are expected to take into account all relevant perspectives.

    When inviting input from declared stakeholders, then, it is important that government not limit discussions to those who have a clear financial interest at stake. Moreover, it is also important that procedures reflect the different amounts of power associated with different stakeholder positions. Industries with significant financial investments and hopes for major profits may have far greater resources to support education and training of their representatives than do volunteer groups of concerned citizens. The former may also have more influence with politicians and policy makers, greater access to the media to get their message across, and more experience in negotiations. When dealing with stakeholder groups, then, it is important to seek procedures that will reflect the degree of interest represented by participants and that will strive to avoid distortion by powerful specific interest groups.

  6. Moral Dimensions (2): Concepts

    While a morally appropriate process is an essential component of good policy in the morally complex realm of biotechnology, it cannot operate in a vacuum. We need some substantive moral values to help guide the process and sort out the morally acceptable from the morally problematic solutions available. Above (Section 3), I argued above that all the leading moral theories have something to contribute to our deliberations in this regard. I shall not, however, attempt the very large project of presenting the various moral theories that can shed light on various moral aspects of biotechnology policy. Instead, I will focus on two key concepts – autonomy and justice – that are central to most of the dominant moral theories. Because of their prominent role in so many ethical theories, these two concepts represent an important element of the substantive requirements of moral deliberation in setting public policy. By exploring some of the ways these concepts function within different moral theoretical perspectives, and also within public policy debates, I hope to make them accessible as valuable tools for identifying and responding to the complex moral demands of setting biotechnology policy.

    In pursuing analysis of these concepts I shall again diverge from the framework provided by the Consultation documents, since they pay very little attention to either autonomy or justice. The role of these concepts there is, largely, an implicit one, appearing – presumably – under the generic label of “the values of Canadians” and inherent in general expressions of the importance of ensuring that the benefits of biotechnology accrue to Canadians.

    Because there is significant variation in how each of these concepts is interpreted even by ethicists, I will spend some time reflecting on how each term should operate in the context of discussions regarding national policymaking in biotechnology. I shall first introduce the most common usage of each term and then propose an alternative, “relational” interpretation that captures some of the neglected moral dimensions of the dominant approach. I will argue that the latter, less familiar interpretation captures essential moral dimensions to be addressed when setting biotechnology policy and better captures the spirit of the procedural recommendations.

    1. Autonomy

      The term “autonomy” literally means self-rule; it is frequently translated as selfdetermination. The term is at the heart of much modern philosophical literature ranging from ethics and political philosophy to metaphysics and personal identity theory; its interpretation varies depending on the context in which it appears. For my purposes here, I shall limit discussion to its role in ethics and political debates. Within this context, the term is popularly understood to represent individual liberty or freedom from interference by others, especially by the state. Respect for individual autonomy is a touchstone of modern liberal states; it is often expressed in the language of human rights (Kymlicka 1990).

      In its most basic meaning, autonomy represents action that is free from controlling influence by others (literally “heteronomy” or rule by others) through coercion or manipulation. Generally, it is used to represent action that is also free from personal limitations (e.g., compulsion, lack of understanding) that prevent meaningful choice. Philosophers typically treat it as an expression of deliberate action on the part of a rational, independent agent, who is acting in pursuit of her chosen interests. Hence, a principle of respect for autonomy is a commitment to recognizing the right of individuals to make certain sorts of decisions for themselves free of coercion, manipulation, deceit, or interference. In health care contexts, the principle of autonomy is often asserted in opposition to paternalism – the practice by which health care professionals make treatment decisions based on their own idea of what is in their patients’ best interests without obtaining voluntary informed consent from the patients (Beauchamp and Childress 1994). Governments also sometimes act paternalistically, for example when they override personal preferences and compel citizens to use seat belts or wear motorcycle helmets in order to protect them from preventable serious injury.

      Although there is not much use of the term “autonomy” in the Consultation documents, there is, at least, an implicit recognition of the importance of autonomy considerations running throughout the documents. For instance, the central document has a section titled “Ethical and Social Aspects” which speaks of Canadian “beliefs regarding freedom, human dignity and non-discrimination” (CBS 1998a, 11). It also refers explicitly to the context created by the Canadian Constitution and the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, documents that place high priority on respect for individual autonomy.

      When the term “autonomy” is explicitly used in the Consultation documents, it is defined very narrowly as being equivalent to consumer choice. This definition occurs in a list of prominent ethical principles and values that are identified as important in other countries’ approaches to biotechnology. In that context individual autonomy is defined as “recognition of each individual’s right to make informed decisions about his or her use of biotechnology” (CBS 1998a, 12; CBS 1998b, 7). Indeed, the importance of supporting consumers’ informed choice in the use of biotechnology is described as central to the entire consultation process: “A key question at the heart of biotechnology discussions is the matter of consumer confidence and comfort with the new DNA-based technologies” (CBS 1998a, 3). The first goal listed in the post-consultation Report is to “ensure that Canadians have access to, confidence in and benefit from safe and effective biotechnology products and services” (CBS 1998b, 8).

      Interpreting autonomy as informed personal choice reflects a popular understanding of the concept as it is frequently invoked in political contexts. This usage captures deeply held views about citizens’ relationship to the state. It speaks specifically to the need to restrict the state from undue interference in individuals’ pursuit of their personal preferences. One of the common assumptions of the modern democratic state is that there must be a sphere of individual privacy outside of the reach of state intrusion. Thus, there is virtual consensus within Canada on the view that the state should refrain from interfering in matters of personal freedom unless there is a very clear risk of harm to specific others.26 Many proponents of the decriminalization of abortion have embraced this notion of autonomy, framing their position as one of being “pro-choice” in support of women’s right to make their own decisions regarding pregnancy continuation or termination. Autonomy language is often used to assert individual rights against state interference with matters of personal morality and action.

      This basic interpretation of autonomy looms large in many debates about biotechnology policy (e.g., Geller 1995; Goldworth 1999; Haseltine 2000; Karjaleinen 1995; McCullough 1998). Both producers and consumers (current and potential) tend to appeal to the idea of personal choice as the appropriate policy governing biotechnology. Both groups resist the very idea that government might impede their ability to buy or sell products and services according to their personal judgments about what is in their best interests. There is significant public support for the view that autonomy, in the sense of freedom from government restriction, should be the default position. In other words, people should be free to sell and purchase products as they see fit unless there is an overriding reason for government to limit commerce in this area.

      There are, of course, many sources of overriding reason. They include unacceptably high risks to consumers (e.g., heroin), threats to the environment (e.g., the transportation of radioactive materials), threats to the fabric of Canadian society (e.g., hate literature), and so on. The burden of proof, however, is always on those who would argue that the potential harms are too large to allow individuals the freedom to choose to purchase the product in question. The principle of autonomy interpreted as freedom of consumer choice suggests a position diametrically opposed to that of the precautionary principle. It implies that so long as someone chooses to buy a given product or service, producers should be free to sell it unless clear and specific harms can be proven.

      This interpretation of autonomy as consumer choice fits nicely within the framework of the marketplace where the primary concern is to protect individual freedom of choice to acquire desirable services and products. (Recall the statement of purpose in the Roundtable Discussion Document CBS 1998a that a fundamental goal of public discussion is to increase “consumer confidence and comfort.”) According to this consumer model of freedom, the role of the state is two-fold. The state has the responsibility of ensuring that the risks associated with specific products are within acceptable levels, a duty frequently interpreted to mean that the risks faced by immediate consumers are reasonable. It also has the responsibility to make certain that individuals are able to choose well by having access to clear, comprehensive, and reliable information and being free from coercion. The various Consultation Documents focus heavily on these two types of concerns.

      It is undoubtedly important to meet the requirements of the consumer model of autonomy in setting biotechnology policy. That is, it is essential that the marketing of any biotechnology products be done under conditions that ensure consumers can make voluntary, informed decisions. In fact, much of the literature that discusses moral considerations associated with biotechnology focuses on concerns of safety and standards of information (e.g., Parker and Gettig 1995; Modell 1996; Masood 1999; Hoskins et al 1995). These criteria are not straightforward, however. Consider the requirement for sufficient information to make an autonomous choice in the context of genetic testing. It is very difficult to make sense of genetic information about susceptibility to particular types of disease. It demands understanding of probability theory, genetics, the range of symptoms associated with the condition in question, the safety and efficacy of early interventions, and many other factors (Parens 1996; Boetzkes 1999; Dickens et al 1996; Gannett 1999). Most experts insist that genetic testing can only be responsibly provided in the context of excellent genetic counseling (Biesecker 1998; Marteau and Bisecker 1999), but there are not enough trained counselors available to meet the demand of genetic tests already available, let alone those on the near horizon.

      In the context of genetically modified foods, many people demand labels that would inform consumers that the products before them contain genetically altered products. Yet labels are unlikely to produce the level of understanding required for informed choice regarding what specific modifications are involved and what their implications might be. For example, how much explanation is required for informed choice regarding the purchase of a candy bar containing genetically modified canola oil? Moreover, in many cases the knowledge base does not exist to provide information on the long-term safety of consumption, the effects of the new species on the environment, or the possibility of new allergies arising from transgenic alterations (Lagay 1999; Lappé 1994; Reiss 1998). It is questionable whether informed choice is even possible in the absence of such important information.

      Furthermore, even if we could provide adequate information, it might still not ensure informed consumer choice. That would require that the information be provided in a form that is accessible to the consumer. If the language of labeling is too technical for the intended audience, the mere presence of information is no assurance that consumers are informed to the level required for autonomous consent. And if the information is incomplete or distorted, as is common in advertising, then it may well undermine rather than support autonomy.27 Even on the most straightforward conception of autonomy, then, selling many biotechnology products to consumers who cannot be adequately informed represents a violation of their autonomy. Canadians need a regulatory system to ensure that their assumptions of consumer safety are well founded and to help promote the understanding necessary to constitute informed consumer choice.

      Important though informed choice is to achievement of individual autonomy, it is not the whole story of autonomy. After all, it is not choice per se that merits moral concern; rather, it is the freedom of individuals to pursue their fundamental values and interests. The underlying moral motivation for respecting individual autonomy is not to support pursuit of preferences per se but to respect each individual’s interest in furthering her or his fundamental values.

      There are several reasons why the exercise of informed consumer choice may fail to capture this deeper sense of autonomy. One difficulty is that consumer choice is limited to the options that producers happen to make available; unless producers provide options that allow individuals to pursue their fundamental values and interests, consumer choice will not coincide with individual autonomy. For example, if all or most farmers are persuaded to plant genetically modified crops or to grow transgenic animals for sale, individual consumers will lose the freedom to buy unmodified food products. Already, many processed foods in Canadian supermarkets contain ingredients made from genetically modified products such as canola oil (Luoma 2000). Even if labelling regulations were introduced, most consumers would likely find it difficult to avoid the use of all forms of genetically modified products. Moreover, if the crops produced by genetically modified seeds prove invasive to other crops, or if they allow purchasers to produce crops at vastly reduced rates for a few years, independent farmers may be unable to continue to plant traditional seeds in an economically viable way. If it is not economically possible to produce unmodified crops, or if distribution of such crops is limited by restrictive arrangements with major producers, individual consumers will not have access to the products they might wish to obtain. In such ways, new products sometimes reduce, rather than expand, consumer choices.

      There are further difficulties with the consumer choice interpretation of autonomy. It ignores the fact that individual agents are differently situated with respect to the choices that are available to them and the freedom each has to act in accordance with his or her particular needs and values. For example, women’s ability to make informed choices about using various prescription drugs is limited by research protocols that sometimes investigate only the drug’s impact on male subjects (Mastroianni et al 1994). Also, access to organically grown food is restricted to people with sufficient land to grow their own food or with enough disposable income to pay the higher premiums on organic food. If consumers remain wary of the safety of genetically modified foods, we can anticipate that the affluent may be able to exercise their choice and buy “traditional” foods, but the poor will be limited to less popular (and, hence, less expensive) alternatives. While all individuals face limits on the options they can choose, those with relatively less social or economic power are likely to face even more restrictions than most people; they will more often find themselves with no option before them that will meet their particular interests and needs.

      As we have seen, many technologies carry with them the power to redefine “normal” human experience and expectations in ways that individuals cannot control through private acts. As individuals, we cannot control whether or not our bodies will be culturally read as sites for medical surveillance. While an individual may be able to choose not to undergo certain diagnostic tests, she cannot choose the ways various parts of her body (e.g., her breasts or bones) and her life cycle stage are defined as potential sites of serious illness. A woman whose sister, mother, or aunt contracts breast cancer may object to being tested for BRCA 1, but if her physician, insurer, or employer judge such tests desirable, she will find her breasts and genes the proposed targets of surveillance whether or not she consents to testing. Once employment of a particular type of technology becomes widely understood as constituting normal and responsible healthpromoting behaviour, individuals who decline it automatically become classified as irresponsible (ColeTurner 1998; Geller et al 1997; Harper et al 2000). That means that as tests for genetic predispositions to late onset disease (e.g., heart disease, colon cancer, Alzheimer’s disease) become available, they may carry with them cultural expectations that responsible individuals ought to undergo such procedures as a matter of routine health care.

      Hence, our understanding of personal autonomy must address the ways that it can be undermined by political, economic, social, and cultural policies that are well beyond the reach of individual choice. If we truly wish to promote individual autonomy, we need to develop policies that will allow all individuals room to pursue their own values and interests. These policies must not only attend to the preferences that people express in the face of a pre-defined array of options, but also investigate the nature of the choices that are made available to them. We must not lose sight of the fact that prevailing social circumstances and political and economic policies influence the range of choices that are available to individuals and that these choices may well be different for members of different social groups. In other words, protecting and promoting autonomy requires more than refraining from interference in the pursuit of current preferences. It also requires active attempts to foster the conditions under which all individuals can pursue their fundamental values and interests.

      This alternative conception, called “relational autonomy” is an approach that views individual persons as socially embedded, with identities forged within the contexts of personal and political relationships and shaped by a range of social determinants such as gender, race, and class (Sherwin 1998, Mackenzie and Stoljar 2000). It requires that we look beyond the individual as she or he is presently constituted and explore the social conditions that support (or inhibit) each person’s ability to identify and pursue her or his own interests. From this level, it appears that there is reason to consider how the very availability of certain types of choices, and the absence of others, can interfere with some individuals’ ability to be self-determining (or autonomous). This interpretation requires investigation at the societal level of ways to promote the types of technologies that will foster personal autonomy and ways to restrict technologies and products that interfere with personal autonomy. It suggests thoughtful consideration about the social, as well as physical, impacts of proposed new technologies. Developing biotechnology policies that are responsible to the concerns of relational autonomy will require careful attention to the procedural requirement of including frequently marginalized social perspectives.

      Furthermore, even an enriched relational understanding of autonomy is not by itself a sufficient moral basis for setting public policy. It must be reconciled with other relevant moral values. For example, we need to be aware of the fact that individual interests frequently conflict with society's interests. Such analysis is evident in the final report of The Royal Commission on New Reproductive Technologies (Royal Commission 1992). The Commission observed that many approaches to assisted reproduction pose a danger of treating (some) women and children as commodities. Hence, it urged speedy passage of legislation (still pending) that would limit the scope of personal choice in some reproductive practices by prohibiting commercial traffic in reproductive materials and services (e.g., gametes, embryos and gestational services). It understood that without such restrictions many infertile individuals and couples would find it difficult to refrain from engaging in commercial transactions to facilitate their quest for children.

      And as we have already observed, personal choices regarding some types of biotechnology use will have financial impacts on other members of society. Provincial governments in Canada have the unenviable task of setting priorities for spending scarce health care dollars; clearly, they cannot provide all requested resources. Introduction of many new technology-intensive approaches to health care is already putting dangerous pressure on limited health budgets. Yet, as many important Canadian reports have noted (e.g. the Lalonde Report, the Ottawa Charter, the Report of the National Forum on Health, and Health Canada’s recent Women’s Health Strategy Report), technological medical interventions in the face or threat of illness is only one component of a proper health agenda. To promote health, governments must also undertake various positive efforts aimed at such factors as environmental safety, supportive social conditions (e.g. economic, physical and emotional security) and modifications of individual behaviour (e.g. diet, exercise and avoidance of tobacco). We must be mindful not to let individual preferences for (bio)technological approaches to human health exhaust resources that are better directed at addressing social determinants of health. This observation brings us into the realm of the other central moral value: justice.

    2. Justice

      Autonomy is an individual-centered value, even on a relational interpretation. It focuses our attention on the choices and actions of individuals and it urges us to grant moral status to the informed choices of individuals. But society is composed of many individuals and, as we know, their values and interests do not always coincide. Hence, a full moral analysis must also find ways of reconciling the interests of all individuals. The concept of justice provides the theoretical basis for this comparative dimension of moral reasoning and action. Justice, like respect for autonomy, is considered a fundamental value of modern liberal states. It, too, can be seen at the heart of the Canadian Constitution and Charter of Rights and Freedoms.

      Like autonomy, the term “justice” is also subject to many diverse interpretations associated with different theoretical perspectives. At the most basic level, the term means fair, equitable, or appropriate treatment, such that each individual receives what he or she is entitled to. Typically, philosophical discussions of justice are divided between two different senses: retributive or distributive. Retributive justice is concerned with people getting what they deserve, be it punishment or reward. It involves both criminal justice and rectificatory justice (compensating people who have been wronged). This sense of justice has limited currency in the context of biotechnology policy. It would come into play in setting up mechanisms to provide for penalties to be assigned for the manufacture and distribution of products that cause harm to people or the environment. Such issues are best addressed through legal channels. From a moral point of view it is only necessary to observe the importance of ensuring access to legal challenges and reasonable financial relief for damages caused by new technologies.

      Most discussions of justice and biotechnology policy are structured by the notion of distributive justice (e.g., Fleck 1998; Karjaleinen 1995; Lappé 1994). Distributive justice is concerned with ensuring a fair distribution of the benefits and burdens that fall on a group (which may be a family, a community, or an entire nation). Questions of distributive justice generally arise under conditions of scarcity and competition. Most theorists accept a form of Aristotle’s formal principle of justice that requires us to treat similar cases similarly and dissimilar cases differently. The task is to determine what constitutes a morally relevant criterion for similar or different treatment. In other words, the substantive problem of distributive justice requires us to determine what is the right principle of distribution for the benefit (or burden) at issue. For example, Canadians generally view the principle “to each according to need” as appropriate for distribution of health care benefits, but most prefer the principle “to each according to merit” for distribution of desirable jobs and salary levels, and “to each according to ability to pay” for luxury items. For distributing burdens, some useful principles are “from each an equal share,” “from each according to ability,” and “from each according to use.” The appropriate choice again varies with the nature of the burden (examples, respectively, are military service, progressive taxes, and user fees).

      Biotechnologies raise significant problems of distributive justice. Hence, many authors concerned with ethical problems associated with biotechnologies, especially in the realm of health care, focus on questions of distributive justice (e.g., Caulfield 1998; O’Mathúna 1999; Peters 1998; Steel et al 1999). Typically, they ask who should pay for these expensive new services and who will benefit from them. These are central questions that must be considered before introducing more genetic tests to the Canadian market. For each new genetic test, every province and territory will be confronted by the problem of deciding whether it is morally obligated to absorb the costs of this test in its already dangerously stretched budget. Each must decide whether genetic testing for dispositions to late onset diseases is to be considered a medical need covered by the universality requirement of the Canada Health Act. The alternative is to judge the tests optional and make them available on a fee for service basis like private hospital rooms, dental surgery, and certain types of eye surgery.28

      If provinces do regard genetic tests as medically necessary for some patients, the cost of providing the tests will have an impact on other services now covered. Not only do the tests themselves cost something to administer, but, as noted above, they require significant amounts of counselling to make the results meaningful to patients. Patients who test positive will presumably be entitled to follow-up medical care. For example, if they test positive for BRCA 1, they might choose to undergo prophylactic double mastectomies and removal of their ovaries and also use of expensive preventative drugs. If provinces declare the tests not medically necessary and decline to absorb the costs for all who are eligible, then, unless the tests are made illegal in Canada, they will only be accessible to those who can afford them. If the tests are truly of medical value, this response would be unfair and probably illegal. If they are not of much value, they should not be offered to anyone, especially not to those who are terrified of contracting a serious disease that runs in their family.

      Distributive justice questions in health care must address macro as well as micro allocation problems. That is, they must provide guidance on how to apportion health resources among large scale categories such as preventive measures, diagnosis, acute care, and chronic care services, as well as deciding who should have access to a particular procedure (e.g., hip replacement) and on what basis. Increasingly, health research proceeds under the auspices of private funding (either in conjunction with public funding or on its own). Because private investment is only made on the expectation of eventual profits resulting, and because future profits can be anticipated only when there are marketable goods or services to be distributed, health research is skewed towards technological approaches. Health innovations that depend on social change, such as protection of the environment, improvement of social conditions, improved safety for those at risk of domestic violence, public health measures (such as safe drinking water), health education, and effective mental health services tend not to be amenable to profit-making. If health budgets become absorbed with responding to expensive biotechnology innovations, there is likely to be less money available to pursue proven public health measures such as these. Clearly, there are important questions of distributive justice to be addressed regarding the organization of health research and the introduction of new forms of biotechnology in health care.

      In the area of biotechnology and agriculture, questions of distributive justice concern the implications of patenting traditional and genetically modified seeds and animals such that access becomes more expensive and less available to the poor. Concentration of economic interests in the hands of a small number of multinational corporations that control distribution of seeds, production of chemicals needed to produce growth, and markets for the resulting crops could produce disproportionate burdens on consumers relative to the benefits of producers (RAFI November/December 2000). If the costs of biotechnologysupported innovations in agriculture fall largely on people living at the margins of survival, the questions of justice become particularly acute.

      Important though the questions of distributive justice are, a justice framework that is limited to questions of fair distribution is insufficient to capture all relevant concerns about justice in the area of biotechnology. As Iris Marion Young (1990) argues, the distributive paradigm of justice tends to improperly exclude questions of social justice, particularly those concerned with “the elimination of institutionalized domination and oppression” (p. 15). A focus on distributive justice directs our attention to the allocation of material goods and resources and allows us to ignore the social and institutional structures that influence patterns of distribution. Attention to social justice expands our focus from questions of distribution in which people are viewed as “primarily possessors and consumers of goods to a wider context that also includes action, decisions about action, and provision of the means to develop and exercise capacities” (Young 1990, p. 16). Social goods such as rights, opportunity, power, and self-respect cannot be adequately addressed within a framework designed to govern the distribution of material things. Social justice requires that we reflect on the unjust distribution of these types of social goods in a society plagued by sexism, racism, and other forms of oppression. It requires us to think of ways to provide greater equality in these less tangible benefits that cannot be apportioned in units to discrete individuals as can a quantity of material goods.

      To capture the concerns of social justice we must develop a relational understanding of justice that is parallel to the relational conception of autonomy discussed earlier.29 Here, too, we need to move away from the naïve view of people as discrete, independent individuals, unaffected by their relationships to others. People are not interchangeable abstract entities comparably affected by each policy. Rather, they are socially situated in specific historical circumstances, shaped by their complex social and political relationships. They belong to a variety of social groups and these groups are caught in complex relations of power – especially relations of oppression and domination – with respect to one another. To capture the significance of this phenomenon, we need to look at patterns and processes of distribution over time. To promote justice among individuals we need to identify the ways in which institutional structures disadvantage certain groups and privilege others.

      Attention to social justice guides us towards different questions regarding biotechnology policy than a focus on distributive justice. It expands the agenda from questions of payment and access to one that includes questions of how we can promote greater equality of respect, status, and influence in society. It asks us to look at structural barriers to equality and consider how proposed innovations are likely to affect these features. From the perspective of social justice, it is no longer sufficient to ask whether someone wants a given product and can afford to purchase it. We need also ask how availability of that product or service will affect others, particularly members of oppressed groups. For example, we need to take very seriously the ways that the move to technological solutions to health problems favour the interests of the privileged who can afford such innovations, and disadvantage the poor. The latter face the dual problem of being unable to afford these products and also losing access to basic health requirements (e.g., nutrition) when limited public resources are redirected to provide the infrastructure required by expensive technological approaches. Hence, a social justice framework suggests that we must do more than try to ensure that the poor as well as the rich can get genetic testing; it requires us to address the social as well as the genetic causes of illness.

      The pursuit of genetically modified foods holds out great promise of benefiting the hungry as well as the prosperous. There is reason to fear that, without it, the earth will not be able to generate sufficient supplies of traditional foods to feed the growing human population. Genetically modified foods offer hope of making more efficient use of dwindling supplies of fresh water and arable land. But, as we have seen, unless social justice considerations are pursued, we run the risk of concentrating power in the hands of those who produce the needed technology and increasing the dependence of those who are destitute (Tangwa 1999). No national biotechnology policy can resolve the huge income disparity between the rich and the poor of the world, but it is possible to demand that new innovations be pursued in areas that will increase the relative power of the worst off. For instance, it is possible to ensure that subsistence farmers not be forced to use seeds that work only in conjunction with expensive fertilizers and herbicides. Canada needs a biotechnology policy that is sensitive and responsive to social, as well as distributive, justice concerns.

  7. Responsibilities

    It is very clear that emerging biotechnology will present us with an ongoing series of difficult moral challenges. Individuals cannot control the social and material conditions that structure the options they face. Moreover, many of the preconditions for autonomy and social justice can only be achieved through political action. Hence, it is essential that governments assume the responsibility to regulate and manage these powerful technologies in the interest of their citizens.

    Moreover, as we have seen, citizens expect their governments to protect and promote common goods as well as the public interest of fairly arbitrating among conflicting interests. They also expect them to organize and facilitate collective interests that benefit most citizens and do not violate the rights of anyone. Indeed, these are principal responsibilities for governments. The government is the agent charged with creating and maintaining the institutions required for ensuring pursuit of these different types of goods. Thus, it is responsible for assuming leadership in ensuring that collective and common goods are met, and that the public interest in resolving conflicting interests in a just and fair manner is achieved.

    In order to know how best to do that, government must foster conversations about the appropriate values to use in guiding policies. Indeed, that was the declared intent of the Consultation documents in Canada. But the effort to solicit input was too narrowly directed and too tilted towards industry. It consisted of brief roundtable discussions based on one-sided information. Moreover, government made the unacceptable decision to equate concerned citizens with other “stakeholders” – that is, to treat them simply as one more self-interested voice in a chorus of lobbyists. A better approach would provide interested citizens with the opportunity to become informed about the complex and ambiguous nature of these technologies in order to allow them to speak thoughtfully on the issues. Strategies such as the creation of citizen forums hold more promise of better capturing the values of Canadians than do invitational workshops of specific stakeholders (Koshland 1996; Gaskell et al 2000; Loka 1999; Masood 1999; Priest 2000).

    The Canadian Biotechnology Advisory Committee (CBAC) has been established to help educate Canadians and to promote discussion of the moral and social implications of these new technologies. In order to fulfill its mandate, it must be clear on the ethical criteria to be met by any biotechnology policy. It should, for example, establish its position with respect to the widely adopted precautionary principle. It should also establish clear moral guidelines with respect to the important values of autonomy and justice. Moreover, it must develop morally defensible procedures to ensure that it is sensitive to all relevant moral perspectives and is able to give voice to vulnerable groups who may not be present at important policy forums. This requires that CBAC pursue openness, inclusiveness, and responsiveness in its practices in order to establish the trust of concerned citizens representing perspectives now excluded from direct participation in policy-making.

    Moreover, once it “discovers” national values on these matters, government has a responsibility to enact appropriate policies that are informed by these reflections and conversations. It must pass and enforce legislation that reflects the interests and values of its citizens, particularly the most vulnerable segments of the population. Thus, it is essential to clarify the relationship between CBAC and government policy-makers. Canadians need assurance that once CBAC garners their views, its insights will be influential in setting national policy and its message will not be lost in the differing mandates of the sponsoring ministries.

    There is, of course, a limit to what any national government can accomplish in the realm of biotechnology. The industries involved are not respectful of national boundaries; most are engaged in a global, not a national, marketplace. Producers resist national regulations on the grounds that local restrictions would put them at an unfair economic disadvantage in a competitive global market. They threaten to move production to a different jurisdiction if their interests are ignored. At the same time, consumers use the Internet to shop beyond their national borders, making it almost impossible for governments to prohibit access to any products for which there is a market.

    Just as individuals cannot achieve autonomy in isolation from the activities of others, neither can nations establish industrial strategies in isolation of the policies of other countries. No country can afford an industrial strategy that is too far out of step with those of its neighbours. Hence, our political leaders must move beyond our nation’s borders and lobby on the world stage for international regulations that will promote safe and healthy uses of biotechnology, while prohibiting the development of dangerous forms. Canadians expect their government to exercise leadership within such international bodies as the United Nations (including UNESCO, the United Nations Educational, Social, and Cultural Organization), the World Health Organization, the World Bank, CODEX, and the World Trade Organization with respect to appropriate regulation of biotechnologies.30

    Citizens have responsibilities as well. Although none of us can shape biotechnology policy on our own, we cannot afford to sit quietly by and wait for our government to act responsibly in the realm of biotechnology. In Canada, the conflicting agendas of the many departments responsible for setting the national biotechnology strategy are overwhelmingly weighted toward those whose mission it is to promote, not restrain, industries. As citizens, all Canadians need to educate themselves about both the hazards and the benefits of various biotechnologies. Individually and collectively, we need to make very clear our desire for policies that reflect moral, as well as economic, values.

  8. Conclusion

    Biotechnology presents a great many moral challenges. Some are variations of traditional problems (e.g., the damage agricultural practices do to the existing environment). Others are new (e.g., the difficulty in tracking dietary restrictions through transgenic permutations of food products31). Many of these challenges must be identified and addressed by individual consumers and producers. But many cannot be resolved through private action. Collective action is required if Canadians are to succeed at identifying and responding to the moral challenges of biotechnology. It is the responsibility of government to provide the leadership necessary for conducting this moral evaluation and action.

    This essay has been designed to illustrate some of the moral challenges posed by biotechnology by focusing on two types of technology: genetic testing for susceptibility to particular diseases, and the production of genetically modified foods. It briefly surveys some of the complex advantages and risks associated with each of these types of biotechnology, noting that often the benefits accrue to different people than those who are assigned the risks of a technology. It then provides some of the central components of an ethical framework that can be used to identify and resolve the many moral questions posed by various forms of biotechnology.

    It explores the specific moral obligation of government to protect and promote the public interest defined as protection of individual rights and development of fair procedures for resolving conflicts. It also explores the related notions of common good and collective good. Together, these three concepts make vivid the moral importance of government action in regulating biotechnologies. They provide a moral imperative to set in place principles and procedures (such as a clarification of the precautionary principle) that will protect Canadians (and others) from harm while promoting access to the benefits of biotechnology.

    Next, the paper explores two key components of the proposed ethical framework to be used in developing public policy governing biotechnology:
    1. Development of procedural approaches to ethical deliberation. These involve genuine public consultations and open deliberations that include participation by a wide variety of Canadians, particularly general citizens, stakeholders, representatives of NGOs, and representatives of disadvantaged groups that might be specifically affected by the technology in question.
    2. Development of two concepts (autonomy and justice) that must play a central role in any ethical investigation of biotechnology. Both concepts are explored in their traditional interpretations (respect for individual choice and fair distribution of burdens and benefits). An alternative interpretation of each, described as relational, is also provided and recommended for use in development of biotechnology policy.

    The essay argues that biotechnology policy must be respectful of both these values – autonomy and justice – interpreted relationally as well as traditionally.

    Finally, the essay draws some specific moral conclusions regarding the various responsibilities of the Canadian government, CBAC, and individual citizens in ensuring a morally adequate national biotechnology policy. These recommendations are illustrative and not exhaustive. The essay does not propose to represent a full accounting of the moral considerations and strategies essential to the setting of a national biotechnology policy. Its aim is more modest. It is to provide and illuminate some key elements that are essential components of a morally adequate framework for establishing and pursuing a national biotechnology strategy.

  9. Works Consulted

    • Asch, Adrienne and Gail Geller (1996) “Feminism, Bioethics, and Genetics.” In Susam M. Wolf, ed., Feminism & Bioethics: Beyond Reproduction New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 318-350.
    • Areen, Judith (1985) “Regulating human gene therapy” West Virginia Law Review 88(2): 153-171.
    • Austad, Torleiv (1996) “The right not to know - worthy of preservation any longer? An ethical perspective” Clinical Genetics 50(2): 85-88.
    • Babul R, S Adam, B Kremer, et al. (1993) “Attitudes toward direct predictive testing for the Huntington disease gene: relevance for other adult-onset disorders” JAMA 270: 2321- 2325.
    • Bansal, A, GC Critchfield, TS Frank, JE Reid, A Thomas, AM Deffenbaugh, & SL Neuhausen (2000) “The Predictive Value of BRCA1 and BRCA2 Mutation Testing” Genetic Testing 4(1): 45-48.
    • Beauchamp, Tom L. & James F. Childress (1994) Principles of Biomedical Ethics, Fourth Edition. New York: Oxford University Press.
    • Becker, Gerhold K., ed. (1996) Changing Nature’s Course: The Ethical Challenge of Biotechnology. Hong Kong: Hong Kong University Press.
    • Benhabib, Seyla and F. Dallmayr, eds. (1990) The Communicative Ethics Controversy. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
    • Benn, Stanley I. (1967) “State” in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Paul Edwards, editor in chief; vol. 8: 6-11. New York: Macmillan Publishing Co. Inc. and The Free Press.
    • Bergman, Liesbeth et al. (2000) “Risk and prognosis of endometrial cancer after tamoxifen for breast cancer” Lancet 356: 881-887.
    • Biesecker, Barbara Bowles (1998) “Future Directions in Genetic Counseling: Practical and Ethical Considerations” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 8(2): 145-160.
    • Binedell, Julia, Jo R. Soldan, Jane Scourfield & Peter S.Harper (1996) “Huntington’s disease predictive testing: the case for an approach to requests from adolescents” Journal of Medical Genetics 33(11): 912-918.
    • Birmingham, Karen & Tinker Ready (1999) “Conflict-of-interest problems lead to policy changes” Nature Medicine 5(7): 717-718.
    • Bluman, L.G., B.K. Rimer, D.A. Berry, N. Borstelmann, J.D. Inglehart, K. Regan, J. Schildkraut, & E.P. Winer (1999) “Attitudes, knowledge, and risk perceptions of women with breast and/or ovarian cancer considering testing for BRCA1 and BRCA2Journal of Clinical Oncology 17(3): 1040-1046.
    • Boetzkes, Elisabeth (1999) “Genetic Knowledge and Third-Party Interests” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 8(3): 386-392.
    • Bowman, James E. (1995) “Genetics and racial minorities” in Warren Thomas Reich, ed., Encyclopedia of Bioethics, revised edition. New York, NY: Simon and Schuster Macmillan.
    • Brown, Kathryn (2000) “Biotech speeds its evolution” Technology Review 103(6): 84-90.
    • Bulger, Ruth Ellen (1996) “Biotechnology applications and women’s health issues” in Frederick B. Rudolph & Larry V. McIntire, eds., Biotechnology: Science, Engineering, and Ethical Challenges for the Twenty-First Century. Washington, DC: Joseph Henry Press: 208-221.
    • Caplan, Arthur L. (1994) “Handle with care: race, class, and genetics” in Timothy F. Murphy & Marc A. Lappé, eds. Justice and the Human Genome Project. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, pp. 30-45.
    • Caulfield, Timothy (1998) “The commercialization of human genetics: profits and problems” Molecular Medicine Today 4(4): 148-150.
    • Canadian Biotechnology Strategy (CBS) Task Force. (1998a, February). Renewal of the Canadian Biotechnology Strategy: Roundtable Consultation Document and Resource Documents 1, 2, 3. Available at ( http://biotech.gc.ca/epic/site/cbs-scb.nsf/en/home)
    • Canadian Biotechnology Strategy (CBS) Task Force. (1998b). The Canadian Biotechnology Strategy: An Ongoing Renewal Process. Available at ( http://biotech.gc.ca/epic/site/cbs-scb.nsf/en/home)
    • Cole-Turner, Ronald (1998) “Do means matter? Evaluating technologies of human enhancement” Philosophy and Public Policy 18(4): 8-12.
    • Collins, FS (1996) “BRCA1 – lots of mutations, lots of dilemmas” New England Journal of Medicine 334: 186-188.
    • Daniels, Norman (1994) “The genome project, individual differences, and just health care” in Timothy F. Murphy & Marc A. Lappé, eds. Justice and the Human Genome Project. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, pp. 110-132.
    • DeAngelis, DL (1992) Dynamics in Nutrient Cycling and Food Webs, London: Chapman & Hall.
    • DeGrazia, David (1991) “The ethical justification for minimal paternalism in the use of the predictive test for Huntington’s disease” Journal of Clinical Ethics 2(4): 219-228.
    • Dickens, Bernard M, Nancy Pei & Kathryn M Taylor (1996) “Legal and ethical issues in genetic testing and counselling for susceptibility to breast, ovarian and colon cancer” Canadian Medical Association 154(6): 813-818.
    • Dove, Alan (2000) “Genetic testing of the Other half” Nature Biotechnology 18(5): 479.
    • Dover GA & Flavell, eds. (1982) Genome Evolution, London: Academic Press.
    • Dyson, Anthony & John Harris, eds. (1994) Ethics and Biotechnology. New York, NY: Routledge.
    • Eccles, D.M., D G R Evans, & J Mackay (2000) “Guidelines for a genetic risk based approach to advising women with a family history of breast cancer” Journal of Medical Genetics 37: 203-209.
    • Emanuel, Ezekiel J. & Linda L. Emanuel (1997) “Preserving community in health care” Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law 22(1): 147-184.
    • FAO/WHO (2000) “Safety aspects of genetically modified foods of plant origin.” Report of a Joint FAO/WHO Expert Consultation on Foods Derived from Biotechnology.
    • Fears, Robin, & Erik Tambuyzer (1999) “Core ethical values for European Bioindustries” Nature Biotechnology 17(2): 114-115.
    • Fleck, Leonard (1998) “Justice, rights, and Alzheimer disease genetics” in Stephen G. Post & Peter J. Whitehouse, eds. Genetic Testing for Alzheimer Disease: Ethical and Clinical Issues. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, pp. 190-208.
    • Fleck, Leonard M (1994) “Just genetics: a problem agenda” in Timothy F. Murphy & Marc A. Lappé, eds. Justice and the Human Genome Project. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, pp. 133-152.
    • Fletcher, J.C. (1998) “The long view: how genetic discoveries will aid healthcare reform” Journal of Women’s Health 7(7): 817-823.
    • Foster, Kenneth R., Paolo Vecchia, and Michael H. Repacholi (2000) “Science and the Precautionary Principle” Science vol. 288, issue 5468 (May 12): 979-981.
    • Foucault, Michel (1973) The Birth of the Clinic. New York: Vintage.
    • Fox, JL (1996) “Insecticide preservation policy: to be or not to Bt” Nature Biotechnology 14: 687-698.
    • Gannett, Lisa (1999) “What's in a Cause? The Pragmatic Dimensions of Genetic Explanations” Biology and Philosophy 14(3): 349-374.
    • Gaskell, George, et al. (2000) “Biotechnology and the European Public” Nature Biotechnology 18(9): 935-938.
    • Geller, Gail, Misha Strauss, Barbara A. Bernhardt & Neil A. Holtzman (1997) “‘Decoding’ informed consent: insights from women regarding breast cancer susceptibility testing” Hastings Center Report 27(2): 28-33.
    • Geller Gail, Barbara A. Bernhardt, K Helzlsouer, Neil A. Holtzman, M Stefanek & PM Wilcox (1995) “Informed consent and BRCA1 testing” Nature Genetics 11: 364.
    • Goelen, G., A. Rigo, M. Bonduelle, & J. De Greve (1999) “Moral concerns of different types of patients in clinical BRCA1/2 gene mutation testing” Journal of Clinical Onclology 17(5): 1595-6000.
    • Goldsmith, Edward et al (1992). The Future of Progress: Reflections on Environment and Development Berkeley, CA: International Society for Ecology and Culture.
    • Goldsmith, Edward and Nicholas Hildyard (1990) The Earth Report 2: Monitoring the Battle for our Environment London: Mitchell Beazley.
    • Goldworth, Amnon (1999) “Informed Consent in the Genetic Age” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 8(3): 393-400.
    • Golub, Edward S. (1996) “Ethical considerations arising from economic aspects of human genetics” in Becker, Gerhold K., ed. Changing Nature’s Course: The Ethical Challenge of Biotechnology Hong Kong: Hong Kong University Press, pp. 71-83.
    • Gorenstein, Hartley (1996) “The regulation of biotechnology in Canada: Social and moral issues” Medical Law International 2(2): 169-182.
    • Grace, Eric S. (1997) Biotechnology Unzipped: Promises and Realities. Washington DC: Joseph Henry Press.
    • Greely, Henry T. (1998) “The Human Genome Diversity Project: Ethical, Legal, and Social Issues” in Peters, Ted, ed. Genetics: Issues of Social Justice Cleveland, Ohio: Pilgrim Press, pp. 71-81.
    • Harper, Peter S, Caron Lim & Craufurd David (2000) “Ten years of presymptomatic testing for Huntington's disease: the experience of the UK Huntington's Disease Prediction Consortium” Journal of Medical Genetics 37: 567-571.
    • Headings, V.E. (1997) “Revisiting foundations of autonomy and beneficence in genetic counseling” Genetic Counseling 8(4): 291-294.
    • Held, Virginia (1984) Rights and Goods: Justifying Social Action. New York: The Free Press.
    • Ho, Mae-Wan (1987) “Evolution by process, not consequence: implications to the new molecular genetics for development and evolution” Int. J. Comp Psychol. 1: 30-27.
    • Hoskins KF, JE Stopfer, KA Calzone, et al. (1995) “Assessment and counseling for women with a family history of breast cancer” JAMA 273:577-85.
    • Hubbard, Ruth & RC Lewontin (1996) “Pitfalls of Genetic Testing” The New England Journal of Medicine 334(18): 1192-1194.
    • Huggins, Marlene, Maurice Bloch, Shelin Kanani, Oliver W.J. Quarrell, Jane Thielmann, Amy Hedrick, Bernard Dickens, Abbyann Lynch & Michael Hayden (1990) “Ethical and legal dilemmas arising during predictive testing for adult-onset disease: the experience of Huntington disease” American Journal of Human Genetics 47(1): 4-12.
    • Iles, Alastair (1996) “The Human Genome Project: A Challenge to the Human Rights Framework” Harvard Human Rights Journal 9: 27-60.
    • Inglehart J.D., A. Miron, BK Rimer, EP Winer, D. Berry, & M.J. Shildkraut (1998) “Overestimation of hereditary breast cancer risk” Annals of Surgery 228(3): 375-384.
    • Jeungst, ET (1997) “Caught in the middle again: professional ethical considerations in genetic testing for health risks” Genetic Testing 1(3): 189-200.
    • Kavka, Gregory S. (1994) “Upside risks: social consequences of beneficial biotechnology” in Carl F. Cranor, ed. Are Genes Us? The Social Consequences of the New Genetics. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
    • Kahn, J. (1997) “Ethical issues in genetic testing for Alzheimer’s disease” Geriatrics 52 (Suppl.2): S30-32.
    • Karjaleinen, Jukka-Mikko (1995) “Justice, Dignity, Autonomy” in Viggo Mortensen, ed. Life and Death: Moral Implications of Biotechnology. Geneva: WCC Publications.
    • Kielstein, Rita (1996) “Clinical and ethical challenges of genetic markers for severe human hereditary disorders” in Becker, Gerhold K., ed. Changing Nature’s Course: The Ethical Challenge of Biotechnology Hong Kong: Hong Kong University Press, pp. 60-71.
    • Kinder, Barbara K (1998) “Genetic and Biochemical Screening for Endocrine Disease: II. Ethical Issues” World Journal of Surgery 22(2): 1208-1211.
    • Khoury, M.J. (1996) “From genes to public health: the applications of genetic technology in disease prevention. Genetics Working Group” American Journal of Public Health 86(12): 1717-1722.
    • Koggel, Christine M. (1998) Perspectives on Equality: Constructing a Relational Theory. Lautham: Rowman & Littlefield.
    • Koshland, Daniel E. (1996) “Ethical decision making in a pluralistic society” in Frederick B. Rudolph & Larry V. McIntire, eds., Biotechnology: Science, Engineering, and Ethical Challenges for the Twenty-First Century. Washington, DC: Joseph Henry Press: 191-198.
    • Kymlicka, Will (1990). Contemporary Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    • Lagay, Faith L. (1999) “Science, Rhetoric, and Public Discourse in Genetic Research” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 8(2): 226-237.
    • Lappé, Marc A. (1994) “Justice and the limitations of genetic knowledge” in Timothy F. Murphy & Marc A. Lappé, eds. Justice and the Human Genome Project. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, pp.153-158.
    • Laublichter, Manfred D (1999) “Frankenstein in the land of Dichter and Denker” Science 286 (3 December): 1859-1860.
    • Lebacqz, Karen (1998) “Genetic privacy: no deal for the poor” in Ted Peters, ed. Genetics: Issues of Social Justice. Cleveland, Ohio” Pilgrim Press, pp. 239-254.
    • Lippman, Abby (1991) “Prenatal genetic testing and screening: Constructing needs and reinforcing inequities” American Journal of Law & Medicine XVII (1&2): 15-50.
    • Lippman, Abby (1998) “The Politics of Health: Genetization versus health promotion” in Susan Sherwin et al. The Politics of Women’s Health: Exploring Agency and Autonomy. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
    • Loka Institute (1999) “Danish-style, citizen-based deliberative ‘consensus conferences’ on science & technology policy worldwide” (http://www.loka.org/)
    • Luoma, John R. (2000) “Pandora’s Pantry.” Mother Jones January-February: 53-59.
    • Lynch, H.T., S.J. Lemon, C. Durham, S.T. Tinley, C. Connolly, J.F. Lynch, J. Surdam, E. Orinion, S. Caster-Slominki, P. Watson, C. Lerman, P. Tonin, G. Lenoir, O. Serova, & S. Narod (1997) “A descriptive study of BRCA1 testing and reactions to disclosure of test results” Cancer 79(11): 2219-2228.
    • MacKay, Charles R. (1991) “The physician as fortune teller: a commentary on ‘The ethical justification for minimal paternalism’” Journal of Clinical Ethics 2(4): 228-238.
    • Mackenzie, Catriona and Natalie Stoljar, eds. 2000. Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self. New York: Oxford University Press.
    • Mahowald, Mary B. (1997) “Gender justice in genetics” Women’s Health Issues 7(4): 230-233.
    • Marteau, Theresa M. & Barbara Bowles Biesecker (1999) “The future of genetic counselling an international perspective” Nature Genetics 22(2): 133-137.
    • Masood, Ehsan (1999) “Britain opens biotech regulation to greater public involvement” Nature 399(May 27): 287-288.
    • Mastroianni, Anna C., Ruth Faden, and Daniel Federman, eds. (1994) Women and Health Research: Ethical and Legal Issues of Including Women in Clinical Studies. 2 vols. Washington, D.C.: National Academy Press.
    • McCullough, Laurence B (1998) “Molecular medicine, managed care, and the moral responsibilities of patients and physicians” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 23 (1): 3- 9.
    • Mikkelson, TR, B Andersen, RB Jorgensen (1996) “The risk of crop transgene spread” Nature 80: 31.
    • Miller, Henry (1997) Policy Controversy in Biotechnology: An Insider’s View. Stanford, California: Academic Press.
    • Modell, Stephen M. (1996) “Framework for the selection of subjects in human gene therapy and diagnostic trials” Journal of Investigative Medicine 44(5): 228-237.
    • Motluk, Alison (1998) “Unusual suspects: will justice suffer if the police rely too heavily on DNA testing?” New Scientist 158(2135): 18-19.
    • Murphy, Timothy F. & Marc A Lappé (1994) Justice and the Human Genome Project. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.
    • Murray, Thomas H & Jeffrey R Botkin (1995) “Genetic Testing and Screening: Ethical Issues” in Warren Thomas Reich, ed. Encyclopedia of Bioethics: Revised Edition, Volume 2. New York, NY: Simon & Schuster Macmillan, pp. 1005-1011.
    • O’Mathúna, Dónal P. (1999) “Applying Justice to Genetics” in Thomas J Demy & Gary P Stewart, eds. Genetic Engineering: A Christian Response: Crucial Considerations in Shaping Life. Grand Rapids, MI: Kregel Publications: pp. 50-69.
    • Parens, Erik (1996) “Glad and terrified: on the ethics of BRCA1 and 2 testing” Cancer Investigation 14(4): 405-411.
    • Parker, Lisa S. & Elizabeth Gettig (1995) “Ethical issues in genetic screening and testing, gene therapy, and scientific conduct” in Floyd E Bloom & David J Kupfer, eds., Psychopharmacology: The Fourth Generation of Progress. New York, NY: Raven Press: 1875-1881.
    • Paulkaitis, P & MJ Roossinck (1996) “Spontaneous change of a benign satellite RNA of cucumber mosaic virus to a pathogenic variant” Nature Biotechnology 14: 1264-1268.
    • Peters, David A. (1998) “Risk classification, genetic testing, and health care: a conflict between libertarian and egalitarian values?” in Ted Peters, ed. Genetics: Issues of Social Justice. Cleveland, Ohio” Pilgrim Press, pp.205-217.
    • Peters, Ted, ed. (1998) Genetics: Issues of Social Justice Cleveland, Ohio: Pilgrim Press.
    • Phillips K.A., E. Warner, W.S. Meschino, J. Hunter, M. Abdolell, G. Glendon, I.L. Andrulis, & P.J. Goodwin (2000) “Perceptions of Ashkenazi Jewish breast cancer patients on genetic testing for BRCA1 and BRCA2” Clinical Genetics 57(5): 376-383.
    • Pimm, SL (1991) Balance of Nature – Ecological Issues in the Conservation of Species and Communities, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
    • Plows, Charles W. et al. (1998) “Multiplex Genetic Testing” Hastings Centre Report 28(4): 15-21.
    • Pollara Research and Earnscliffe Research and Communications (2000) “Public opinion research into biotechnology issues: overall narrative”. Presented to the Biotechnology Assistant Deputy Minister Coordinating Committee (BACC), Government of Canada. (http://strategis.ic.gc.ca)
    • Priest, Susanna Hornig (2000) “US public opinion divided over biotechnology?” Nature Biotechnology 18(9): 939-942.
    • Quaid, Kimberly A. (1991) “Predictive testing for HD: maximizing patient autonomy” Journal of Clinical Ethics 2(4): 238-240.
    • RAFI (March/April 2000). Communique. “Suicide Seeds on Fast Track: Terminator 2 Years Later.” Available at (www.rafi.org).
    • RAFI (September/October 2000). Communique #67. “Golden Rice and Trojan Trade Reps: A Case Study in the Public Sector’s Mismanagement of Intellectual Property.” Available at (www.rafi.org).
    • RAFI (November/December, 2000). Communique Issue # 67. “Biotech's 'Generation 3'.” Available at (www.rafi.org).
    • Raikka, Juha, Veikko Launis & Juhani Pietarinen, eds. (1999) Genes and Morality. Amsterdam: Rodopi.
    • Redden, Candace Johnson (1999) “Rationing care in the community: engaging citizens in health care decision making” Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law 24(6): 1363- 1389.
    • Reiss, Michael (1998) “Biotechnology” in Ruth Chadwick, ed. Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics, Volume 1. Toronto: Academic Press, pp. 319-333.
    • Rennie, John (1994) “Grading the Gene Tests” Scientific American 270(6): 88-97.
    • Rhodes, R. (1998) “Genetic links, family ties, and social bonds: rights and responsibilities in the face of genetic knowledge” Journal of Medical Philosophy 23(1): 10-30.
    • Rothstein, Mark A. (1996) “Ethical issues surrounding the new technology as applied to health care” in Frederick B. Rudolph & Larry V. McIntire, eds., Biotechnology: Science, Engineering, and Ethical Challenges for the Twenty-First Century. Washington, DC: Joseph Henry Press: 199-207.
    • Royal Commission on New Reproductive Technologies. 1992. Proceed with Care, vols. 1 and 2.
    • Rudolph, Frederick B & Larry V McIntire, eds. (1996) Biotechnology: Science, Engineering, and Ethical Challenges for the 21st Century Washington, D.C.: Joseph Henry Press.
    • Sagar, Ambuj, Arthur Daemmrich & Mona Ashiya (2000) “The tragedy of the commoners: biotechnology and its publics” Nature Biotechnology 18(1): 2-4.
    • Sass, Hans-Martin (1996) “Moral risk assessment in biotechnology” in Becker, Gerhold K., ed. Changing Nature’s Course: The Ethical Challenge of Biotechnology Hong Kong: Hong Kong University Press, pp. 127-144.
    • Schrag D., K.M. Kuntz, J.E. Garber, & J.C. Weeks (2000) “Benefit of prophylactic mastectomy for women with BRCA1 or BRCA2 mutations” JAMA 283(23): 3070-3072.
    • Schroten, Egbert (1998) “Ethical aspects of genetic modification of animals: opinion of the Group of Advisers on the Ethical Implications of Biotechnology of the European Commission” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 7(2): 194-198.
    • Sherwin, Susan (1998) “A relational approach to autonomy in health care” in Susan Sherwin et al. The Politics of Women’s Health: Exploring Agency and Autonomy, Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
    • ___________ 1999. “Foundations, Frameworks, Lenses: The Role of Theories in Bioethics.” Bioethics 13:3, 4 (July): 198-205.
    • __________ 2000. “Feminist Reflections on the Role of Theories in a Global Bioethics.” In Rosemarie Tong, Gwen Anderson, and Aida Santos, eds. Globalizing Feminist Bioethics Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press (in press).
    • Shiva, Vandana (1993) Monocultures of the Mind, Penang: Third World Network.
    • Shulman, Seth (2000) “Toward sharing the Genome” Technology Review 103(6): 60-69.
    • Smith, David, Kimberly A. Quaid, Roger B. Dworkin, Gregory P. Gramelspacher, Judith A. Granbois & Gail H. Vance (1998) Early Warning: Cases and Ethical Guidance for Presymptomatic Testing in Genetic Disease. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
    • Steel, M, E. Smyth, H. Vasen, D. Eccles, G. Evans, P. Moller, S. Hodgson, D Stoppa- Lyonnet, J. Chang-Claude, M. Caligo, P. Morrison, & N. Haites (1999) “Ethical, social and economic issues in familial breast cancer: a compilation of views from the E.C. Biomed II Demonstration Project” Dis Markers 15(1-3): 125-131.
    • Takala, Tuija (1999) “The Right to Genetic Ignorance Confirmed” Bioethics 13(3-4): 288-293.
    • Tangwa, Godfrey B. (1999) “Globalisation or Westernisation? Ethical concerns in the whole bio-business” Bioethics 13(3-4): 218-226.
    • Thompson, Paul (2000). “Food and Agricultural Biotechnology: Incorporating Ethical Concerns.” Available at (www.cbac-cccb.ca).
    • United Nations (1992) Rio Declaration on Environment and Development, June 13 (U.N.Doc./CONF.151/5/Rev.1).
    • Vandana, Shiva & Ingunn Moser, eds. (1995) Biopolitics: A Feminist and Ecological Reader on Biotechnology. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Zed Books.
    • Vanderzwaag, David (1999) “The precautionary principle in environmental law: elusive rhetoric and first embraces.” Journal of Environmental Law and Practice 8 (13): 355- 375.
    • Wakeford, Tom (1998) “Citizen foresight: Public participation in Biotechnology” BINASNews 4(1), (http://www.bdt.org.br/binas/News/98issue1.html#s1)
    • White, Mary Terrell (1999) “Making Responsible Decisions: An Interpretive Ethic for Genetic Decisionmaking” Hastings Center Report 29(1): 14-21.
    • Winfield, Tom (1996) “An Engo perspective on the biotechnology risk assessment debate” Canadian Institute for Environmental Law and Policy. Available at: (http://www.isb.vt.edu/brarg/brasym96/winfield96.htm)
    • Wingspread. 1998. Statement on the Precautionary Principle. Available at: (http://www.sehn.org/wing.html)
    • Young, Iris Marion (1990) Justice and the Politics of Difference, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    • Zimbelman, Joel (1996) “Technology assessment, ethics and public policy in biotechnology: the case of the human genome project” in Gerhold K. Becker, ed. Changing Nature’s Course: The Ethical Challenge of Biotechnology Hong Kong: Hong Kong University Press, pp. 85-107.

  1. 1 With assistance from Patrycja Maksalon.
  2. 2 Moreover, Canadian government policy has viewed some areas of biotechnology as sufficiently distinct as to require their own ethical analysis. For example, human reproductive and related genetic technologies have merited a Royal Commission study and an advisory committee to the Deputy Minister of Health. Research in biotechnology involving human (or animal) subjects has been primarily addressed under procedures governing all types of human (or animal) subject research.
  3. 3 Although these documents were created with the specific purpose of initiating public discussion at a given point in time, they have not yet been replaced by extensively revised documents that reflect the outcome of public consultations. There is a single, brief summary document that was prepared immediately after the public consultations (CBS 1998b). This follow-up document proposes virtually identical policy proposals while addressing fewer issues with less depth of analysis than the earlier set of Consultation Documents. Moreover, it has had a very limited distribution. Hence, I shall primarily rely on the more widely known Consultation Documents (CBS 1998a) as the most complete expression to date of Canadian government understandings and attitudes regarding biotechnology.
  4. 4 This same wording is repeated in the document produced in response to that public consultation process (CBS 1998b), p.2.
  5. 5 As Reiss 1998 demonstrates, most literature follows this practice of reserving the term “biotechnology” for new genetically-based technologies.
  6. 6 For example, the Statement of the 1998 Canadian Biotechnology Strategy (CBS 1998b) simply states: “All Canadians – producers and consumers across the country, including people in smaller communities and rural areas – will benefit from the new transformation.” (p. 2) It is completely silent on the possibility of harms inherent in this technology.
  7. 7 A recent European study has concluded that prescribing tomoxifen for women who have not yet contracted breast cancer but are considered high risk for future disease creates an unacceptably high risk of endometrial cancer for them (Bergman et al. 2000).
  8. 8 Moreover, there is the possibility of inaccurate results according to which false positive or false negative results triggers inappropriate conclusions and mistaken actions. See Collins 1996; Eccles 2000; Inglehart et al 1998.
  9. 9 The complexity of gene activity and interaction is well known in science but tends to be downplayed in public promises about the fruits of genetic research. See, for example, Dover and Flavell 1982; Ho 1987; Miller 1997; Pollard 1988.
  10. 10 See, for example, the report released last year by Health Canada entitled “Health Canada’s Women’s Health Strategy” (1999).
  11. 11 Many experts insist that these risks are low, but few claim that there are no substantial risks involved. (For a fuller discussion of this and other public concerns agricultural biotechnology, see Thompson, 2000.)
  12. 12 See RAFI (November/December 2000 for development of this view.
  13. 13 In the face of strong public pressure, officers of two of the “Gene Giants,” Zeneca and Monsanto, publicly promised to refrain from commercial development of this technology (Open Letter from Monsanto CEO Robert B. Shapiro to Rockefeller Foundation President Gordon Conway and others, 4 October 1999. On the internet: (http://www.monsanto.com/monsanto/gurt/default.htm). Letter from Dr. D.A. Evans, Research & Development Director, Zeneca Agrochemicals, to Prof. Richard Jefferson, CAMBIA, Australia, dated 24 February 1999, published in UNEP/CBD/SBSTTA/4/Inf.3 Supplementary information to UNEP/CBD/SBSTTA/4/9/Rev.1, 'Consequences of the Use of the New Technology for the Control of Plant Gene Expression for the Conservation and Sustainable Use of Biological Diversity, 18 May 1999. Shapiro 1999). Nonetheless, despite opposition from the public, national governments and the United Nations, nearly 40 patents exist in this area and testing of this technology is proceeding. Harry Collins, the vice-president of the principal company involved (Delta and Pine Land Seed Company) has announced “We never really slowed down. We are on target, moving ahead to commercialize it. We never really backed off.” (RAFI March/April 2000).
  14. 14 Ethics of care requires us to investigate the implications of our policies for meeting human needs and promoting healthy relationships among people. Feminist ethics directs us to seek policies that will reduce rather than exacerbate the effects of existing patterns of systematic oppression in society.
  15. 15 One of the expressed goals is to “position Canada as an ethically and socially responsible world leader in the development, commercialization, sale and use of biotechnology products and services” (CBS 1998b, 9).
  16. 16 It is not difficult, however, to imagine that some people’s short term interest in unfettered market access as either producers or potential consumers of specific product might interfere with their ability to recognize the benefits to them of such a system.
  17. 17 Evidence that Canadians’ expect such stewardship from their government can be found in Pollara and Earnscliffe (2000). They conclude that “there is a general presumption that someone, somewhere, is in charge of monitoring and regulating food safety” and that most Canadians “would re-balance government activity to provide a dual focus for government: to limit or regulate practices in order to minimize risks, and to promote development so as to maximize benefits.”
  18. 18 In CBS 1998b Annex A: Ten Key Themes in the CBS Workplan, items 2, 4, 5, 6, 8, and 10 are clearly focused on efforts to promote well-being while items 3 and some aspects of 1 and 7 seem to focus primarily on protection against harms.
  19. 19 D. Vanderzwaag (1999) has identified fourteen different formulations in treaties and other declarations.
  20. 20 See Winfield 1996.
  21. 21 In fact, one particular theoretical position in ethics – communicative ethics – can be seen as primarily committed to procedural strategies. See Benhabib and Dallmayr 1990.
  22. 22 For examples of global moral considerations, see Marteau and Biesecker 1999; Sagar et al 2000; Tangwa 1999.
  23. 23 They may, for instance, be denied access to life or health insurance unless they agree to be tested.
  24. 24 For example, those who have close relatives with breast cancer will have a different perspective on the desirability of introducing nationwide testing for BRCA1 and BRCA2 than citizens who are concerned with the implications of such tests on public attitudes towards geneticization and existing health care budgets.
  25. 25 The controversy over the patenting of Basmati rice is documented in several publications available at the RAFI website: (http://www.etcgroup.org/).
  26. 26 Its most famous expression in Canada was provided by Prime Minister Pierre Elliot Trudeau, who introduced sweeping changes to the sexuality provisions in the Criminal Code in 1969 with the caveat that the state has no business in the bedrooms of the nation.
  27. 27 A major reason for federal laws prohibiting direct to consumer advertising of prescription drugs is that evidence shows such advertising almost always misleads the public into a false understanding of the advantages and risks of the drugs in question.
  28. 28 In some cases, medical services that would fall under the medical necessity requirement, such as some types of chemotherapy, are simply not offered to anyone rather than have them available on a fee for service basis only to those who can afford them.
  29. 29 A relational account of equality and its relevance for a theory of justice is spelled out in detail by Christine Koggel (1998).
  30. 30 The post-consultation document makes explicit the Canadian government’s sense of commitment to working through these international channels (CBS 1998b, 6).
  31. 31 For instance, some people who avoid eating animal products for spiritual or health reasons may be uncomfortable with the prospect of eating vegetables that have been modified to resist frost damage through incorporation of cold-resistant genes from penguins or Arctic char.
http://cbac-cccb.ca


    Created: 2005-07-13
Updated: 2007-06-28
Top of Page
Top of Page
Important Notices